P
PseuTonym
Guest
Introduction:
Consider the set of odd numbers between zero and ten. Let’s give the name u to that set.
We can write u = {1, 3, 5, 7, 9}.
Is the number 2 an element of u? In attempting to answer that question, we might pay attention to the following:
Thm(2 isn’t odd).
In other words, the statement “2 isn’t odd” is a theorem. Of course, you will not find something so trivial in Euclid’s Elements with the label “theorem.” In Euclid’s Elements, it would not even get the label “proposition.” However, we are using the word “theorem” to indicate simply that “2 isn’t odd” has been deduced from our axioms, and we don’t intend to include any connotation that the result is interesting, difficult or important.
For convenience, let us give the name P(t) to the property (t is an integer and t is odd and t is between zero and ten). When we replace the variable t with a specific value, P(t) becomes a statement.
The reason that we are interested in Thm(2 isn’t odd) is that it implies the following:
Thm(not P(2))
Question up for debate:
Is there a connection between Thm(not P(2)) and the fact that 2 isn’t an element of u?
ZF will be arguing that there is no connection.
Powerful argument number one:
ZF: “The actual connection is between (not P(2)) and the fact that 2 isn’t an element of u. That Thm(not P(2)) happens to be true is a random coincidence. Ordinary mathematical practice does not require proofs or theorems. Yes, they exist, but they are very rarely available. Ordinarily, people who are using mathematics simply make direct appeals to their mathematical intuition. Fortunately, we are all members of one species, and the human genetic endowment provides us with accurate intuition about mathematics. For example, our Pythagorean genes provide us with the intuition that tells us that the Pythagorean thing is indeed a fact.”
Powerful argument number two:
ZF: “When you say that something is a theorem, that is merely philosophical commentary about math. There can be no connection worthy of the name between the solid, pure mathematical truth that 2 isn’t an element of u, and the vague, confused, philosophical label of theorem. Ordinary mathematical practice involves direct appeals to intuition, as I have already explained. On rare occasions, somebody might prove a theorem. However, it would be a reckless practitioner of mathematics who went beyond the act of proving a theorem, and actually used the word “theorem” (or any abbreviation for that word) as part of the practice of mathematics. No, that would be commentary outside of mathematics. The first rule of Proving Theorems Club is: you do not claim that something is a theorem. The second rule of Proving Theorems Club is: you do not claim that something is a theorem.”
Powerful argument number three:
ZF: “Suppose that we use the notation u = {t: P(t)}. That notation makes reference to P(t), but it doesn’t mention Thm. Whatever is omitted from a notational abbreviation is also omitted from the thing that is being abbreviated. For example, four factorial is supposedly equal to 4 times 3 times 2, but you don’t see a factor of three anywhere in the expression 4!, do you? No, I didn’t think so. So four factorial is a number that is not divisible by 3. Nor do we see the word “not” anywhere in the notation u = {t: P(t)}. So it cannot tell us that something is not an element of u. At best it can tell us that some things are elements of u. Furthermore, I don’t see any vowels in the weird expression “Thm.” You can use the word “theorem” if you want to violate the first and second rules of the Proving Theorems Club, but you have to write all the vowels in that word.”
Consider the set of odd numbers between zero and ten. Let’s give the name u to that set.
We can write u = {1, 3, 5, 7, 9}.
Is the number 2 an element of u? In attempting to answer that question, we might pay attention to the following:
Thm(2 isn’t odd).
In other words, the statement “2 isn’t odd” is a theorem. Of course, you will not find something so trivial in Euclid’s Elements with the label “theorem.” In Euclid’s Elements, it would not even get the label “proposition.” However, we are using the word “theorem” to indicate simply that “2 isn’t odd” has been deduced from our axioms, and we don’t intend to include any connotation that the result is interesting, difficult or important.
For convenience, let us give the name P(t) to the property (t is an integer and t is odd and t is between zero and ten). When we replace the variable t with a specific value, P(t) becomes a statement.
The reason that we are interested in Thm(2 isn’t odd) is that it implies the following:
Thm(not P(2))
Question up for debate:
Is there a connection between Thm(not P(2)) and the fact that 2 isn’t an element of u?
ZF will be arguing that there is no connection.
Powerful argument number one:
ZF: “The actual connection is between (not P(2)) and the fact that 2 isn’t an element of u. That Thm(not P(2)) happens to be true is a random coincidence. Ordinary mathematical practice does not require proofs or theorems. Yes, they exist, but they are very rarely available. Ordinarily, people who are using mathematics simply make direct appeals to their mathematical intuition. Fortunately, we are all members of one species, and the human genetic endowment provides us with accurate intuition about mathematics. For example, our Pythagorean genes provide us with the intuition that tells us that the Pythagorean thing is indeed a fact.”
Powerful argument number two:
ZF: “When you say that something is a theorem, that is merely philosophical commentary about math. There can be no connection worthy of the name between the solid, pure mathematical truth that 2 isn’t an element of u, and the vague, confused, philosophical label of theorem. Ordinary mathematical practice involves direct appeals to intuition, as I have already explained. On rare occasions, somebody might prove a theorem. However, it would be a reckless practitioner of mathematics who went beyond the act of proving a theorem, and actually used the word “theorem” (or any abbreviation for that word) as part of the practice of mathematics. No, that would be commentary outside of mathematics. The first rule of Proving Theorems Club is: you do not claim that something is a theorem. The second rule of Proving Theorems Club is: you do not claim that something is a theorem.”
Powerful argument number three:
ZF: “Suppose that we use the notation u = {t: P(t)}. That notation makes reference to P(t), but it doesn’t mention Thm. Whatever is omitted from a notational abbreviation is also omitted from the thing that is being abbreviated. For example, four factorial is supposedly equal to 4 times 3 times 2, but you don’t see a factor of three anywhere in the expression 4!, do you? No, I didn’t think so. So four factorial is a number that is not divisible by 3. Nor do we see the word “not” anywhere in the notation u = {t: P(t)}. So it cannot tell us that something is not an element of u. At best it can tell us that some things are elements of u. Furthermore, I don’t see any vowels in the weird expression “Thm.” You can use the word “theorem” if you want to violate the first and second rules of the Proving Theorems Club, but you have to write all the vowels in that word.”