Nonetheless, the thought of hell, and even of being predestined to hell (that I do not accept) has been seen as important by different denominations, like the Reformed Calvinists, and the Anglicans, the Anglicans in articles X (denying free will), XVI (setting up something very close to a double predestination).
I see no double predestination in XVI. I see something pretty close to the Thomist position–a very careful affirmation of single predestination and single predestination only. Nor do I see Article 11 as saying anything significantly different from the Council of Trent on this point. I would argue that the Articles represent a moderate Reformed position that (on this particular set of issues–obviously not on others) is practically indistinguishable from Catholic Thomism.
That being said, I have never professed allegiance to the Articles–I subscribe to them insofar as they are compatible with the faith of the Universal Church, and no further.
Denial of hell, however, at any level, means denial that our actions have real and dire consequences. The wicked who prosper in this world really do prosper. Even if we accept that there is temporary punishment, we deny God’s justice, for it is justice that those outside His grace should be dealt with according to their merits achieved outside His love, which are none, for they would not exist without His love.
To me that points toward a doctrine of annihilation.
To destroy the soul creates even more problems, for God made the soul to be eternal in its essence, and in destroying souls, God would violate completely the nature of what He created.
Perhaps, although Justin Martyr and other early Christians categorically deny the “natural immortality” of the soul. Perhaps it is different when you see nature as something created by God (which I don’t think the pagan Platonists did exactly). However, I find more useful the idea (which may amount to the same thing) that God doesn’t take back His gifts–rather, if we misuse them they remain in effect and become something twisted and powerful for evil.
It is important to remember, when wrestling with the real difficulties of reconsiling hell with God’s love and mercy, that we do have a free will (at least those of us who have reached an age of reason), and freely choose either God’s grace, or its lack, which can only be outside His perfect presence.
And that’s where Thomists often seem to me to be playing with words. If those who are not elect are inevitably going to choose to reject God and be damned, then it’s hard not to see “free will” as an empty phrase–which was essentially Calvin’s position (i.e., he didn’t deny that there was a kind of free will, but he didn’t see that it was relevant for a discussion of soteriology). The Wesleyan concept of universally offered prevenient grace, whatever its problems, at least allows free will to have some meaning while preserving the Augustinian doctrine that human beings can’t turn back to God of themselves. I know that the sufficient/efficient grace distinction is supposed to do the same thing, but again I find it an empty formula.
What evil would God be willing?
Since evil is a privation of good, it would appear that if God does not choose to cause a good that belongs to the nature of some creature, He is in some sense willing the privation of that good to exist. I.e., if God does not choose to cause a good will in human beings, He is permitting them to fall short of the good for which they were made. I understand that there is a difference between permission and active will, and I would not say that it is meaningless. But it is not particularly helpful in avoiding the charge of God causing evil, it seems to me, particularly since evil is not a thing in itself (and thus really cannot be willed as an object).
I am unfamiliar with this view. What is it?
A short version of it is found
here. The full text used to be available on the Internet–I couldn’t find it just now. Another brief treatment, however, is
here.
In Christ,
Edwin