P
polytropos
Guest
In such a society, the homosexual acts do not lead to procreation; it is the homosexual acts together with a consummating heterosexual act that leads to procreation. The homosexual act itself is non-procreative in the same sense that a masturbatory act is non-procreative in the example I gave.Sure, but then in what sense does gay sex thwart procreation? It’s conceivable, in a given society, that the people who have gay sex are the same ones who procreate (heterosexually, of course), and that nobody who refrains from sodomy has children. In such a case, how can one argue that homosexual acts necessarily thwart procreation? (We must have the “necessarily” there because the premise is not supposed to be based on likelihoods).
Here is (3) again:
- Homosexual acts use the sexual organs in ways that thwart procreation.
This is definitely an area I have to think about a bit more. The procreative/unitive understanding is what the new natural lawyers propose. I tend to side with the old natural lawyers, but the old natural lawyers unfortunately have not published nearly as much work on the matter. I’m not really aware of any recent systematic treatment of sexual ethics from an old natural law perspective.This is all a good point, but Premise #1 could be easily reworked without mentioning unitive-ness, if we just put it in the form of a necessary condition, as you suggest. Or we could mention the unitive condition – which means we have to explain how gay relationships aren’t unitive in the relevant sense (not an easy sell, perhaps).
But I think that the procreative dimension itself is not sufficient, at least if it is interpreted as implying that any act that leads to some form of procreation is moral, while any act that does not is immoral. Then there is a minefield of issues one must navigate with things like premarital sex, infertile couples, etc. One could probably make due with the concept of procreation alone if one were to emphasize to a greater extent procreative-type acts rather than procreative tokens. An infertile couple is still essentially procreative in the same sense that a brain-dead patient is still essentially rational, whereas a homosexual couple is no more procreative than a doorknob. (I borrow this point from Bill Vallicella, who notices that there is a difference between infertility and not being fertile.)
None of this is very clear, but… I’ll think about it.
I agree to some extent. But I think such an argument would still require a spirited attempt as severing the association of happiness with preference satisfaction and emotion.Or else, if social acceptance of homosexuality severs the link between homosexual activity and unhappiness, I guess my argument would fall apart (or, as you say, require an obscure understanding of happiness). But in that case, I must say, I would be theologically puzzled. I don’t know of any other type of sin that doesn’t usually make people more unhappy and dissatisfied, in the long run. I don’t know why God would create an action with a tendency toward happiness, and then forbid it.
I do think there are some sins that don’t make people unhappy and dissatisfied (in the modern sense). For example, pirating of music and movies is absolutely rampant today. I have many friends who pirate digital content with no qualms; I even used to do it until I realized what I was doing while reading an examination of conscience sheet. But of course: there is little feeling of consequence when one pirates. One obtains the desired content immediately. And one retains money to spare. I don’t think people who engage in such an activity generally start to feel unhappy.