E
Elf01
Guest
We still have to define directly killing.The moral object is twofold – save five and directly kill one.
We still have to define directly killing.The moral object is twofold – save five and directly kill one.
The distinctions made against Fr. Tad’s definitions of direct and indirect has now been refuted. Specifically, 1) the moral object is independent of any particular agent’s intention, and 2) the proximate end of the act includes all deliberated moral outcomes.We still have to define directly killing.
The moral object discloses what the act targets, the intentions of any particular actor notwithstanding. The object of the act is the same for the disinterested bystander as it is for another bystander who hates the innocent one and intends to kill.Clearly the innocent person is killed by the trolley, the trolley was sent down the track when the switch was thrown, and throwing the switch with knowledge of that consequence was deliberate. *If my distinction between direct and indirect is valid then “ saving the five ” is the direct effect, and all subsequent effects - including running over the one - are indirect. The object of the action would be “ switching the trolley away from the five ”. The effect on the five is therefore direct since they are defined in the object. The effect on the one is indirect because he is not part of the object.
No, you should not.I can switch a lever and direct the train to another rail where only one person is. Should I do it even though I would be directly responsible for one death?
What post are they in again?The distinctions made against Fr. Tad’s definitions of direct and indirect has now been refuted. Specifically, 1) the moral object is independent of any particular agent’s intention, and 2) the proximate end of the act includes all deliberated moral outcomes.
I have never made such a farcical claim. What I said was, that since the object included the proximate end, and an end is in fact intended, there is an intent in the object. That is not the final end, which would be the intent font.You persisted in this misinterpretation that the proximate end not only proceeded from the agent’s intent but was identical to it, throughout this thread (and in 2017) even when several challenged you.
You mean this error?But, OK. Let’s move on to the error in the idea that “the proximate end” must be singular.
You apparently don’t distinguish object from objectives. The objectives would be the intent, not the object, and nowhere is there an intent to kill one. “Save five” is not an object in the sense the word is used in this discussion. An object is an act and its proximate end.The moral object is twofold – save five and directly kill one.
Now that we agree that the moral object has two effects, we can apply Ender’s rule for “direct” vs. “indirect”.What post are they in again?
The definition of the object includes an effect and that effect is direct, subsequent/consequent effects are indirect.
Clearly the innocent person is killed by the trolley, the trolley was sent down the track when the switch was thrown, and throwing the switch with knowledge of that consequence was deliberate.
You apparently do not read the authoritative citations provided.You apparently don’t distinguish object from objectives. The objectives would be the intent, not the object, and nowhere is there an intent to kill one. “Save five” is not an object in the sense the word is used in this discussion. An object is an act and its proximate end.
In fact the object is neither of these, let alone both of them. The intent is to save the five. The object is to divert the trolley away from the five. The consequences are that five are saved and one dies.
Perhaps reading your own posts would show how it is possible to make such hash. Hash in, hash out.I don’t know how it is possible to make such a hash out of my comments …
To which you replied:The primary determinant or source of the moral status of
an act is the act’s “moral object.”1 The object of a moral
act is the specific kind of action or behavior chosen.
The moral status of an act’s object is independent of the
person choosing.
Ignoring that citation, you proceed to once again define the moral object font as dependent on the intent of the actor, the actor whose intent you prefer.Your citation of The Moral Fonts of Action and Decision Making is interesting but not clarifying …
(1) and (2) cannot both be true as the one contradicts the other. What is a deliberated moral outcome if not and end, an objective…an intent? In fact you’ve already contradicted (1) in post #863:
- the moral object is independent of any particular agent’s intention, and
- the proximate end of the act includes all deliberated moral outcomes.
Ah, I think this might be helpful: is the object the same in both cases? From the viewpoint of someone watching the action there would be no way to differentiate the actions of the bystander who throws the switch to save the five, and the person who throws it to kill the one. From his perspective the actions are identical.The object of the act is the same for the disinterested bystander as it is for another bystander who hates the innocent one and intends to kill.
You cannot properly apply “my” rule where I have explicitly rejected your condition - that is, your contention that a moral object has two effects. I have never accepted that.Now that we agree that the moral object has two effects, we can apply Ender’s rule for “direct” vs. “indirect”.
I think this is the comment that you misperceive. Take murder for example. Murder as an object is always immoral regardless of who does it, or why, but what constitutes murder? In fact murder is defined as intentional killing; intent is a key part of what makes an act murder.The moral status of an act’s object is independent of the person choosing.
A bit of straw in this post. No one has contended that the bystander intends to kill.I think this is the comment that you misperceive. Take murder for example. Murder as an object is always immoral regardless of who does it, or why, but what constitutes murder? In fact murder is defined as intentional killing; intent is a key part of what makes an act murder.
There is no such thing as “moral” object. There is only the “object”, which may or may not be “moral” - based upon all the circumstances, the intent, and means. And, of course the “ethical system” one subscribes to. To call the “object” to be “moral object” automatically skews the whole concept, making it invalid.The consequentialists argue, as you do, (incorrectly) that the moral object includes subjective content and excludes moral content.
Well said – as a consequentialist.There is no such thing as “moral” object. There is only the “object”, which may or may not be “moral” - based upon all the circumstances, the intent, and means. … To call the “object” to be “moral object” automatically skews the whole concept, making it invalid.
I wish you would really think it through. The object, the intent, the means, the outcome, the circumstances are all part of the “moral object”, if and only if TOGETHER they form a morally right action. Moral, of course according to the ethical system one subscribes to.Well said – as a consequentialist.
The moral object is just the physical stuff and can be based on one’s intent. Thanks for confirming my understanding of the errors in the consequentialist’s argument.
What made you think there was anything to talk about with me?… there is nothing to talk about.
Hope of some level of rationality. But actually I wanted to expose your incorrect views.What made you think there was anything to talk about with me?
If only you would understand the term of “consequentialist”. I tried to explain, but maybe I failed. Only someone wearing “blinders” would say that ONLY the outcome (the consequences) count, the rest being irrelevant.If you are an atheist then consequentialism is consistent with your disbelief.
Being a Catholic cannot impose a “must” on someone’s beliefs or opinion.If one is a Catholic then one must believe…
The Church only propose the truth. Faithful Catholic assent. You’re not Catholic. So, again – what’s your point?Being a Catholic cannot impose a “must” on someone’s beliefs or opinion.
Nor was that the point of the comment. It was to demonstrate that there is an intent included in the object. Given that murder is an object, and that for an act to be considered murder the killing has to be intentional it ought to be clear that it must include the intent to kill. In the object. This is not the intent of the killing - why one does it - but the intent that makes it murder in the first place.A bit of straw in this post. No one has contended that the bystander intends to kill.
No one is confused about this, nor has it ever been questioned.i What I think you misunderstand is than any act evil in its object is, by definition, intrinsically evil.
I don’t know what consequentialists argue, but I do know this is not an argument I’ve ever made. Just stick to my comments; don’t attribute someone else’s claims to me.The consequentialists argue, as you do, (incorrectly) that the moral object includes subjective content and excludes moral content.
No, the moral object is corrupted if intent is injected, especially when preferentially injected which is what your latest argument does. That very casuistry is the method the utilitarians use to justify direct abortion.Nor was that the point of the comment. It was to demonstrate that there is an intent included in the object. Given that murder is an object, and that for an act to be considered murder the killing has to be intentional it ought to be clear that it must include the intent to kill. In the object. This is not the intent of the killing - why one does it - but the intent that makes it murder in the first place.
I simply am applying the “duck” principle to your argument. Yes, your argument is precisely consequentialism. At the risk of being ignored once again, I point out your arguments consequentialist errors. Your last candidates for moral object are:I don’t know what consequentialists argue, but I do know this is not an argument I’ve ever made. Just stick to my comments; don’t attribute someone else’s claims to me.
Examine your argument. Read Vertias Splendor’s condemnation of consequentialism. Your first choice at defining the moral object is purely physical lacking moral content (condemned in VS p. 78). Your second choice injects a particular agent’s intention and neglects the inclusion of the evil end foreseen by all agents (condemned in VS p. 79).I struggle to define the object so I’m open to adjustments here, but at the moment this [Throw the switch to divert the trolley] seems right (I could also accept “Throw the switch to divert the trolley away from the five.”)
I suppose o_mlly means this from Veritas Spendor:Ender:![]()
Read Vertias Splendor’s condemnation of consequentialism. Your first choice at defining the moral object is purely physical lacking moral content (condemned in VS p. 78).I struggle to define the object so I’m open to adjustments here, but at the moment this [ Throw the switch to divert the trolley ] seems right (I could also accept “Throw the switch to divert the trolley away from the five.” )
which suggests Ender’s second definition is more appropriate, of which o_mlly says:By the object of a given moral act, then, one cannot mean a process or an event of the merely physical order, to be assessed on the basis of its ability to bring about a given state of affairs in the outside world. Rather, that object is the proximate end of a deliberate decision which determines the act of willing on the part of the acting person.
First of all, VS does not condemn the injection of the agent’s intention, as VS even says “deliberate decision” and “act of willing”, both of which relate to intention. But the “condemnation” o_mlly speaks of would be this from VS:Your second choice injects a particular agent’s intention and neglects the inclusion of the evil end foreseen by all agents (condemned in VS p. 79).
This may be confusing and requires some careful parsing. But it is very well summarized by the paragraph heading: "Intrinsic evil": it is not licit to do evil that good may come of it. It is also sometimes described as “the ends do not justify the means”. But what are the means? They are events that serve to bring about the desired end. Here we must distinguish between means that bring about desired ends and consequences that follow the act, but do not bring about the desired ends. VS only condemns evil means that bring about the desired ends. It does not condemn evil consequences that follow the act but do not bring about the desired ends. In the trolley problem, the death of the one man is clearly in the second category. Yes, it is evil. Yes, it happens as result of diverting the trolley. But the trolley striking the one man dead is not the means of saving the five. It contributes nothing to their safety. It does not assist the bystander in any way in accomplishing the desired end. This makes it just a consequence, not any different from the death of a baby in an ectopic pregnancy after the tube has been removed. By contrast, cutting the baby out of the tube, or dissolving the baby with methotrexate does make the death of the baby the means by which the life of the mother is saved. Therefore that act would be condemned by p. 79 of VS.One must therefore reject the thesis, characteristic of teleological and proportionalist theories, which holds that it is impossible to qualify as morally evil according to its species — its “object” — the deliberate choice of certain kinds of behavior or specific acts, apart from a consideration of the intention for which the choice is made or the totality of the foreseeable consequences of that act for all persons concerned.
The debate in this thread is about the application of Catholic moral theology to an abstract, some would say, frivolous case. Not so. The consequentialist arguments from those who would allow the direct killing of an innocent on the track are identical to those who would allow direct abortions. One such proponent is Rhonheimer:What post are they in again?
The publication below shows Rhonheimer arguments are the same arguments as my interlocutors. The article also clarifies the real difference between “direct” and “indirect” as I posted back in #522:Rhonheimer states that the killing of the infant through a craniotomy [the crushing of the child’s head] is
However, this begs the question again, because he simply declares the craniotomy to be an act good in itself because it saves the life that can be saved.the unwilling consequence of an act that is good in itself—saving the life that can be saved—and perhaps even required. Therefore, the killing should be called non-intentional because it cannot even determine the act on the level of object, since it is not intended. (Rhonheimer 2009b, 40)
After reading the article, please let me know if the clarification you asked for on “direct” and “indirect” is resolved. If not then identify the mediating cause that would allow the innocent one’s death to be “indirectly” caused by the bystander’s act.“Proximate” in moral theology means “unmediated” that is immediately, not in time but absent any intervening causes.
Frankly, a debate over action theory and the meaning of “direct” and “indirect” has been going on for thirty years and during that time it was an interesting debate among highly respected theologians and philosophers. However, it is no longer a topic for debate among theoreticians.
If the action theory proposed by Rhonheimer is accepted, it could be very difficult to avoid death-dealing actions from taking place in Catholic hospitals.
Rhonheimer appears to be saying that a chosen human action can be indifferent; that is, it can have no inherent moral character. However, this assumption simply does not comport with any moral theory developed and utilized by the magisterium.
Rhonheimer continues to confuse the moral issues by the way in which he formulates them.
Rhonheimer wants to make his moral judgment solely on the basis of intention, prescinding from what actually occurs in the physical world of cause and effect. … This simply cannot be a correct interpretation of the encyclical.
Not so. A distinction has been shown again and again. It is has to do with the distinction between the means to an end a consequence that is not a means. In direct abortion, the death of the baby is the means to some end. In the trolley problem the death of the one on the track is not the means to anything. It is a consequence. Lumping the the two uses together is over-simplification as it ignores this difference.The debate in this thread is about the application of Catholic moral theology to an abstract, some would say, frivolous case. Not so. The [consequentialist] arguments from those who would allow the direct killing of an innocent on the track are identical to those who would allow direct abortions.
The article cited did not define “indirect” in terms of a mediating cause. Indeed the word “mediating” only appears once in the article, and not in the context of defining “indirect”. However the article does mention “indirect” 16 times, and in all those 16 times it appears consistent with the bystander’s action in the trolley problem.After reading the article, please let me know if the clarification you asked for on “direct” and “indirect” is resolved. If not then identify the mediating cause that would allow the innocent one’s death to be “indirectly” caused by the bystander’s act.
No, if anything the article by Mr. Hass supports the arguments of o_mlly’s interlocutors. Indirect is used by Mr. Hass to describe the removal of a cancerous uterus:The publication below shows Rhonheimer arguments are the same arguments as my interlocutors.
The death of the child when the uterus is removed is foreseen just as the death of the man on the tracks is foreseen when the bystander throws the switch. One might try to argue that the two cases are different because the man would not die if the switch were not thrown, whereas the child is expected to die. However that is not a significant difference, as the fate of the child in the uterus is not known, only surmised. If the cancer is small enough, it is entirely possible that he might be born alive if left alone.An example of a so-called indirect abortion would be the case of a pregnant woman who is suffering from uterine cancer. The cancerous uterus must be removed to save the life of the mother even though it is foreseen that the child will die. Such an intervention would be permitted by the principle of double effect.